当前位置: 首页 > 期刊 > 《英国医生杂志》 > 2004年第25期 > 正文
编号:11356608
Medical researchers' ancillary clinical care responsibilities
http://www.100md.com 《英国医生杂志》
     1 Department of Clinical Bioethics, National Institutes of Health, 10 Center Drive, Bethesda, MD 20898, USA

    Correspondence to: LBelskylbelsky@mail.cc.nih.gov

    Investigation of participants in clinical trials may identify conditions unrelated to the study. Researchers need guidance on whether they have a duty to treat such conditions

    Introduction

    Ancillary care is that which is not required to make a study scientifically valid, to ensure a trial's safety, or to redress research injuries. Thus, stabilising patients to enrol them in a research protocol, monitoring drug interactions, or treating adverse reactions to experimental drugs are not ancillary care. By contrast, following up on diagnoses found by protocol tests or treating ailments that are unrelated to the study's aims would be ancillary care.

    Two extreme views

    When asked how much ancillary care they should provide to participants, the first reaction of many clinical researchers, especially those working in developing countries, is that they must provide whatever ancillary care their participants need. From an ethical perspective, this response makes sense. Research participants in trials in the developing world are typically desperately poor and ill, and everyone arguably has a duty to rescue those in need, at least when they can do so at minimal cost to themselves.2 3 Yet this response fails to acknowledge that the goal of research is to generate knowledge not care for patients.4 5 When researchers consider that offering ancillary care this broadly may drain limited human and financial resources and confound study results, they tend to retreat from this position.

    Some researchers veer to the opposite extreme. "We may be doctors," they note, "but these are our research participants, not our patients, so we owe them nothing beyond what is needed to complete the study safely and successfully—that is, we owe them no ancillary care." But this extreme position is ethically questionable. Consider the case of researchers studying a rare disease. It is ethically unacceptable to say to a participant, "We are going to monitor the toxicity and effectiveness of this experimental drug, and we will make sure it does not kill you, but we are not going to provide any palliative care for your condition." Closely monitoring a participant's disease without being willing to treat it in any way amounts to treating him or her as a mere means to the end of research.

    Hypothetical case: trial of antimicrobials for sexually transmitted diseases in a developing country

    While performing clinical examinations on female patients to check for sexually transmitted diseases or side effects of the antimicrobial drug, researchers are likely to discover many women with vaginal candidiasis.8 More than half are likely to be suffering from the results of poor dental care and hygiene. What care should be provided for these problems?

    Vaginal candidiasis

    This is clearly within the scope of entrustment because the diagnosis results from examinations essential to the research. The underlying duty of care also seems strong because untreated candidiasis will greatly affect their wellbeing and treating it is relatively cheap and easy

    Decision: Researchers ought to treat vaginal candidiasis

    Dental problems

    These are not within the scope of entrustment. If we assume that the poor dental hygiene is apparent on casual observation, its diagnosis would not result from exercising the permission participants granted on entering the study. The question of strength thus does not arise.

    Decision: Dental care falls outside the scope of ancillary care responsibilities

    A better model

    In the partial entrustment model, the scope of entrustment depends on the study. The research protocol, which specifies the information, interventions, tests, and sample required, will determine what permission needs to be obtained. A protocol that collects only a single magnetic resonance image from each participant yields a limited scope of entrustment, pertaining mainly to the researchers' collection and use of the image. A study involving an extended inpatient stay, by contrast, will yield a far broader scope of entrustment.

    How much responsibility do researchers have for conditions not included in the trial?

    Credit: TONKOENE/STILL PICTURES

    Although the scope of this partial entrustment will vary, it is possible to generalise. Since a participant typically gives permission for a disease under study to be monitored, the scope of entrustment typically includes caring, as needed, for that disease. Since participants' permission is needed for doing tests or collecting confidential medical information, the scope of entrustment typically includes following up on any clinically relevant information or diagnoses generated.

    How strong is the entrustment responsibility?

    Researchers and ethics committees should attempt to anticipate the ancillary care responsibilities that will arise in a given protocol. Funding to cover researchers' ancillary care responsibilities must be included in research budgets. Many major research sponsors have been hesitant to fund medical care that is not necessary for the scientific success of a trial. Our hope is that the partial entrustment framework will encourage ethics committees, researchers, and sponsors to regard fulfilling ancillary care responsibilities as an essential part of ethical research.

    Hypothetical case: HIV treatment in tuberculosis treatment trial

    The trial calls for screening out patients who are HIV positive and dropping participants who seroconvert during the trial. The local standard of care for HIV and AIDS includes only palliative care. Do the researchers have a responsibility to help provide antiretroviral drugs to people they find to be HIV positive?

    People screened out because they are HIV positive

    Such people are within the scope of entrustment because the study calls for checking HIV status; but the strength of the duty of care is questionable. Although vulnerability and dependence are high (since HIV infection is deadly and other sources of antiretroviral drugs do not exist), engagement and gratitude are weak because these are not yet research participants.

    Decision: Researchers probably do not have a responsibility to provide drugs

    Participants dropped mid-trial because they seroconvert Treatment is within the scope of entrustment because the study design calls for monitoring HIV status, and the strength of the duty of care is high. Vulnerability and dependence remain high and with enrolled participants engagement and gratitude are greater.

    Decision: Researchers probably have a responsibility to provide antiretroviral drugs

    Summary points

    Researchers need ethical guidance regarding their responsibilities for providing ancillary care to participants

    An ethically acceptable approach would recognise a partial entrustment of participants' health to researchers

    The scope of this entrustment is determined by the permission researchers need to do the study safely and validly

    Whether ancillary care should be provided then depends on the strength of the duty of care

    The strength of the duty of care depends on participants' vulnerability, dependence, and uncompensated risks or burdens and the depth of the researcher-participant relationship

    We thank Ezekiel Emanuel, Christine Grady, Frank Miller, Leif Wenar, and David Wendler, and audiences at the Parasitology and International Programs Branch at NIAID, led by Lee Hall; the Department of Clinical Bioethics; the 3rd Africa Conference on Ethical Aspects of Clinical Research in Developing Countries, Kampala, Uganda; the Kennedy Institute of Ethics, Georgetown University; and the Latin American Conference on Ethical Aspects of International Collaborative Research. Kawango Agot, Kirana Bhatt, Stephen Chanock, Steven Holland, Samia Hurst, Matti Parri, Beyene Petros, Donald Rosenstein, Catherine Slack, and Douglas Wassenaar provided useful written comments and criticisms.

    Contributors and sources: LB and HSR attended the rounds of clinical researchers at the National Institutes of Health and interviewed them about ancillary care issues. In addition, they observed and met clinical researchers in Argentina and Uganda. LB has training in political theory, biology, and international health policy, and HSR is a professor of philosophy at Georgetown University with additional graduate degrees in law and public policy.

    Competing interests: HSR owns shares in various publicly traded pharmaceutical companies.

    References

    Nuffield Council on Bioethics. The ethics of research related to healthcare in developing countries. London, 2002: 97.

    McIntyre A. Guilty bystanders? On the legitimacy of duty to rescue statutes. Philos Public Aff 1994;23: 157-91.

    Scanlon TM. What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1998: 224-8.

    Miller FG, Rosenstein DL, DeRenzo EG. Professional integrity in clinical research. JAMA 1998;280: 1449-54.

    Katz J. Human experimentation and human rights. St Louis Univ Law J 1993;38: 7-54.

    Richardson HS, Belsky L. The ancillary-care responsibilities of medical researchers. Hastings Cent Rep 2004;34: 25-33.

    Pellegrino ED. Nonabandonment: an old obligation revisited. Ann Intern Med 1995;122: 337-78.

    Fitzgerald DW, Behets F M-T. Women's health and human rights in HIV prevention research. Lancet 2003;361: 68-9.(Leah Belsky, fellow1, Hen)